Aesthetics and Art Lecture 7 PHIL 3681/2618 Professor David Macarthur The Traditional Idea of an Author • The traditional idea of the author is as having an authoritative role in determining literary meaning since they made or created it. • Link to biographical criticism and the idea of recovering a fixed unitary meaning from a text: call this Monism. • Authorial Monism: the view that the fixed unitary meaning of the text is the one the author intended – assuming this intention was successfully realized in the text. E.g. Danto. • French philosophers Michel Foucault and Roland Barthes are associated with “the death of the author”. • This is a revolutionary way of thinking about literary texts that dispenses with ANY reference to the author in matters of interpretation. • How plausible is this position? Death of the Author: Michel Foucault & Roland Barthes Death of the Author-God • Note that the death-of-the-author is a variation on Nietzsche’s famous claim that God is dead. Analogy: Ordinary Speech • In an ordinary speech act we have no trouble thinking there is a speaker who intends to convey a meaning by their words to a certain audience: “I’d like an espresso please!” • Plausibly literary acts (e.g. texts) have communicative intentions also. • Artist à literature à intended “meaning” à a suitably sensitive audience recovers that “meaning” by interpreting the text. Art Demands Our Interest • An artwork is an object that demands our attention and interest. • That’s one reason art is often felt to be pretentious. • It also explains why we can feel resentment when art does not fulfill its promise of being especially interesting. Where does our interest lie? Art vs Artist • When we interpret art it is features of the art that we are primarily interested in: its “content” realized in this form. • The artist is, at best, of secondary interest e.g. artistic style, the artist’s oeuvre. • A psychologist may look at artworks as evidence for facts about authors. We can do this too if we want to take a symptomatic stance towards art. • But this is not the way we look at art as art. Expression: Art vs Artist • “Expressivism”: on Collingwood’s theory we focus on the communicability (or clarification) of emotion in an artistic medium – the work’s distinctive emotional expression is made manifest. • We need not put the whole weight on the artist as the source of this expression, as Collingwood does. • Artist’s expression vs the artwork’s expression. We can distinguish these since an artwork is a work of imagination. Qualifying Collingwood • Why can’t an artist make an artwork that has its own emotional expressivity which is not attributable to the artist? • This need not be craft since the artist might explore the expressive power of an artistic medium without having a fully worked out idea of what they are making. • There is the idea of art as having a life of its own. Duchamp spoke about letting his artworks go out into the world, like grown up children. Communicative Action Model of Art • Our response to art is akin to our response to other people. Think about the terms we use to describe art e.g. “mature”, “shallow”, “deep”, “interesting”, “intriguing”, “philosophical”, “all style and no content”… • This motivates treating art as capable of being interpreted along the same general lines as human beings and their actions. • In understanding human action we discover the intention expressed by appeal to the reason-requiring question “Why?” (cp. Wittgenstein, Anscombe). • We employ a principle of charity that aims to make the most reasonable sense of the agent/artwork under the circumstances. Criticism of Barthes • The metaphysical conception of the author as God-of-meaning is arguably a straw man! • Art criticism is not simply a matter of guessing what was on the artist’s mind. • The Cartesian conception of mind, which it seems to presuppose, is flawed. What of the unconscious? • Art as artifact inevitably raises issues of intention, purpose, aim; that is, issues of authorship! Criticism of Barthes • Why put all the emphasis for the production of meaning on either the author or the reader? Why not both! • Caveat: interpretation goes beyond “meaning”. Our interest in art is wider than that e.g. artistic style, use of an art medium. And we can be interested in misfiring art (e.g. B-grade movies). Authorial Intention • Irrelevancy view: the author's intentions are completely irrelevant to interpretation or • No-Authority view: the author’s intentions, although relevant, are not authoritative. • What matters (most?) in criticism is the artist’s intentions as realized in the artwork. That’s only available on the basis of an interpretation of the work, not by asking the artist. • Joke: “You can’t think my novel is bad since I intended to write a good one!” The Nesting of Intention: More or less specificity • The intention to make something – distinguishes the work from natural objects. • The intention to make a work of art – distinguishes art from craft (e.g. jewellery, tools, cars) • The intention to make a work of art of a certain category – distinguishes among different categories of art. • The intention to embody the theme of, say, the vanity and paradoxical nature of human ambition – something that we can discover in the work itself, e.g., Macbeth. The Mind: Descartes On the Cartesian view: • The mind is metaphysically private and fully transparent to itself. • One knows one’s own mind better than anyone else could ever do. • Intention is a willing, an “inner” cause of “outer” behaviour. The Expressive View of Mind: Wittgenstein • The mind is public (not private!) and knowable by others. • Actions express one’s intentions, thoughts and feelings. E.g. gesture, tone, facial expressions. • Intentions are internally related to action explanations. The link is not merely causal but constitutive. Anscombe on Intention • When we describe intentional action we are pointing to something for which reasons can be given. • By ‘reasons’ we do not mean mere ‘causes.’ Two ideas of Intention Distinguish: • Cartesian: Looking for the intention behind the action (artwork), say, in the artist’s ‘mind’. Trying to guess a cause you cannot observe i.e. an hypothesis. • Wittgensteinian: Looking for the intention in the action (artwork). Learning how to read this expression of mindedness. Looking for the reason for doing something. Knowing what one is doing. Action is intentional under a description • A particular action can be intentional under one description, but not intentional under another. • E.g. What I did was to play a DVD… but I (also) caused the baby to wake. • I did not act in order to make the baby wake up but that’s what happened (i.e. a causal effect). • I might not have even known that the baby was asleep in the next room. Intention in Art: Questions • What is artistic intention? (How do we know? Often we can only look to the artwork, not the artist) • How well was it realized? Artistic failures are surely possible. • What is the value of the intention-as- realized? The very idea of art is something that has value, that delivers on the promise of art. Artist as God reprise • Can an artwork have unintended features in the way an action can? • Yes and no. There are no excuses in art. The artist is responsible for everything in the artwork. • So, it seems there is something right about the idea of the author as God after all, the one who is fully responsible for the world of the artwork they have created. • But, note, this is not to say that the artist is the god of meaning. Theories of Interpretation: Monism • MONISM. There is one right interpretation which must be found. Traditionally, this is the author’s own interpretation. • CRITICAL MONISM. There is one right interpretation arrived at on critical grounds. E.g. Nehamas. Theories of Interpretation: Pluralism • Critical Pluralism: Interpretations are partly found and partly created by viewers, a kind of pluralism. • The critical task is to recover the intentions of the artist that frame (without fully determining) plausible interpretations. • The frame constitutes a ‘rational core’ that any reasonable interpretation, however divergent, must agree about. Hence, it captures a monist intuition. Radical Pluralism: “Interpretational Relativism” • Interpretations are created by readers (e.g. Deconstructivism, Barthes) on the basis of experiencing the artwork. • On this view there is no ‘rational core’ that constrains disagreement other than an intention to make art. Even the category of art is in question. • Interpretations are still influenced by past interpretations, critical traditions, cultural norms and so on. • So there may still be considerable overlap between reasonable interpretations but this is now a contingent matter, not a necessary condition. Authorial Intention Distinguish: • the implied author: an abstract function of interpretation. The idea of a “guiding intelligence” responsible for the meaning as expressed in the work. • the writer: an historical figure or figures who causally made the work in question. Reasons for the Distinction i) Multiple authors e.g. the Bible was written by many writers but interpretation still postulates a unitary “implied author”, the ‘voice’ of the text. Cp. Films, architecture, opera. In this case all the creators involved are, as it were, combined into a collective mind. • ii) A distinction can be drawn between what writers say they meant and what the work is plausibly interpreted to mean. • This is so even if, sometimes, one can identify the writer with the implied author. iii) When interpreting art as art our primary interest is in the work, not the artist. • There is a tradition of thinking that the artist ought to disappear (Flaubert). • Recall that Kant says art must appear natural (as if unintended). • This is a normative claim and it seems in tension with Romanticism. • iv) Mere self-display is exhibitionism, something inartistic. • According to Tolstoy, the artist must be sincere so not pandering to an audience. • According to Collingwood, the artist explores their own emotion for themselves. True art is not primarily directed towards a specific audience. Waiting for Godot (1952) Playwright & Implied Playwright Must we think the play’s themes – life as a matter of inventing ways to pass the time, our hopeless hope for ‘metaphysical’ salvation in a pitiless universe, etc. – are ideas Beckett himself is committed to? Obviously NOT! Where to Look for the Meaning? • To Alan Schneider's question 'Who or what does Godot mean?', Beckett replied, 'If I knew, I would have said so in the play.’ • Another occasion when Beckett was asked what the play meant he responded by reading the play. • Beckett: “I produce an object. What people make of it is not my concern [...] I'd be quite incapable of writing a critical introduction to my own works.”
学霸联盟